English
Noun
- A follower of deontology.
Deontological ethics or deontology (
Greek:
δέον (deon) meaning 'obligation' or 'duty') is an approach to
ethics that focuses on
the rightness or wrongness of actions themselves, as opposed to the
rightness or wrongness of the consequences of those actions. Let
justice be done though the heavens fall! is one of its proud
slogans.
It is sometimes described as "duty" or
"obligation" based ethics, because deontologists believe that
ethical rules "bind you to your duty". The term 'deontological' was
first used in this way in 1930, in
C. D.
Broad's book, Five Types of Ethical Theory.
Deontological ethics is commonly contrasted with
consequentialist or
teleological
ethical theories, according to which the rightness of an action is
determined by its consequences. However, it is also important to
note that there is a difference between deontological ethics and
moral
absolutism. Deontologists who are also moral absolutists
believe that some actions are wrong no matter what consequences
follow from them.
Immanuel
Kant, for example, famously argued that it is always wrong to
lie – even if a murderer is asking for the location of a potential
victim. Deontologists who are not moral absolutists, such as W.D.
Ross, hold that the consequences of an action such as lying may
sometimes make lying the right thing to do. Kant's and Ross's
theories are discussed in more detail below.
Deontological ethics
When C. D. Broad first used the term
'deontological' in the way that is relevant here, he contrasted the
term with '
teleological', where
'teleological' theories are those that are concerned with outcomes
or consequences. Broad's main concern was distinguishing the
positions that different ethical theories took on the relationship
between values and right action. He wrote:
[Theories] which hold that there is some special
connexion between [Moral Obligation and Moral Value]....might take
the following forms. The concepts of obligation are fundamental and
the concepts of value are definable in terms of them. Thus it might
be held that the notion of fittingness is fundamental, and that "X
is intrinsically good" means that it is fitting for every rational
being to desire X. Such theories might be called Deontological. The
concepts of value are fundamental, and the concepts of obligation
are definable in terms of them. Such theories may be called
Teleological. E.g., it might be held that "X is a right action"
means that X is likely to produce at least as good consequences as
any action open to the agent at the time. (Bold print not in
original)
Thus, the term 'deontological' picked out the set
of ethical theories that are based on the idea that an action's
being right or wrong is basic, and whether a situation is good or
bad depends on whether the action that brought it about was right
or wrong. To illustrate, imagine that someone can bring it about
that nobody in the world suffers from starvation. However, to do so
they would have to act in a way that was morally wrong. Perhaps,
they would have to kill everyone currently living on land that
could not support agriculture. A deontologist would state that the
way that the end to starvation was brought about would mean that
the 'world without starvation' was a bad state of affairs.
A teleologist, on Broad's use of the term,
explains the rightness of actions in terms of the goodness of the
state of affairs that occurs because of that action. If some action
genuinely brings about greater good in the world, then it is a
right action, and this rightness is independent of the nature of
the action or the intentions of the person carrying out the action.
Broad points out that on this understanding of the distinction
between 'deontological ethics' and 'teleological ethics', not all
utilitarians are telelogists:
'Utilitarianism, in some of its forms, would be
an example of [teleological ethics]. But
[Henry]
Sidgwick, though a Utilitarian, definitely rejects the view
that "right" means "conducive to good".'
The most famous deontological theory of ethics is
that of the German philosopher
Immanuel
Kant. However, the
Divine
Command Theory, also known as 'theological volunterism', is a
form of deontological ethics, and a number of modern philosophers
have also developed deontological ethical theories.
The Divine Command Theory
The 'Divine Command Theory' is
actually a cluster of related theories that state that an action is
right if God has decreed that it is right.
William
of Ockham,
René
Descartes and eighteenth-century
Calvinists all
accepted versions of this moral theory, according to
Ralph
Cudworth, as they all held that moral obligations arise from
God's commands. The Divine Command Theory is a form of deontology
because, according to it, the rightness of any action depends upon
that action being performed because it is a duty, not because of
any good consequences arising from that action. If God commands
people not to work on the Sabbath, then people act rightly if they
do not work on the Sabbath because God has commanded that they do
not do so. If they do not work on the Sabbath because they are
lazy, then their action is not, truly speaking ‘right’, even though
the actual physical action performed is the same. If God commands
that you not
covet your
neighbour’s goods, then even if coveting improves people’s
motivation to achieve things in life, and so has apparently
beneficial outcomes, you should not covet your neighbours goods.
Moreover, a world where people coveted their neighbours’ goods
could not be considered ‘good’, even if people prefer to live in
such a world.
Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant's theory of ethics is
considered deontological for several different reasons. First, Kant
argues that to act in the morally right way, people must act
according to duty (deon). Second, Kant argued that it was not the
consequences of actions that make them right or wrong but the
motives of the person who carries out the action. Kant's argument
that to act in the morally right way, one must act from duty,
begins with an argument that the highest good must be both good in
itself, and good without qualification. Something is 'good in
itself' when it is
intrinsically
good, and 'good without qualification' when the addition of
that thing never makes a situation ethically worse. Kant then
argues that those things that are usually thought to be good, such
as
intelligence,
perseverance and
pleasure, fail to be
either intrinsically good or good without qualification. Pleasure,
for example, appears to not be good without qualification, because
when people take pleasure in watching someone suffering, this seems
to make the situation ethically worse. He concludes that there is
only one thing that is truly good: Nothing in the world—indeed
nothing even beyond the world—can possibly be conceived which could
be called good without qualification except a good will. Kant then
argues that the consequences of an act of willing cannot be used to
determine that the person has a good will; good consequences could
arise by accident from an action that was motivated by a desire to
cause harm to an innocent person, and bad consequences could arise
from an action that was well-motivated. Instead, he claims, a
person has a good will when he or she 'acts out of respect for the
moral law'. People 'act out of respect for the moral law' when they
act in some way because they have a duty to do so. So, the only
thing that is truly good in itself is a good will, and a good will
is only good when the willer chooses to do something because it is
that person's duty. Thus, according to Kant, goodness depends on
rightness.
Kant's three significant formulations of the
categorical
imperative are:
- Act only according to that maxim
by which you can also will that it would become a universal law.
- Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in
your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a
means, but always at the same time as an end.
- Act as though you were, through your maxims, a law-making
member of a kingdom of ends.
W. D. Ross
W. D. Ross has been said to hold a position that
is "representative of pluralistic deontology" Ross argued that
utilitarianism was an inadequate moral theory because it failed to
appropriately account for primary moral concerns: [Utilitarianism]
seems to simplify unduly our relations to our fellows. It says, in
effect, that the only morally significant relation in which my
neighbours stand to me is that of being possible beneficiaries of
my action. They do stand in this relation to me, and this relation
is morally significant. But they may also stand to me in the
relation of promisee to promisor, of creditor to debtor, of wife to
husband, of fellow countryman to fellow countryman, and the like;
and each of these relations is the foundation of a...duty....
Ross's pluralism is also apparent in this quote. He argues that
there are seven right making features of moral action:
- Duty of beneficence: A duty to help other people (increase
pleasure, improve character)
- Duty of non-maleficence: A duty to avoid harming other people.
- Duty of justice: A duty to ensure people get what they deserve.
- Duty of self-improvement: A duty to improve ourselves.
- Duty of reparation: A duty to recompense someone if you have
acted wrongly towards them.
- Duty of gratitude: A duty to benefit people who have benefited
us.
- Duty of promise-keeping: A duty to act according to explicit
and implicit promises, including the implicit promise to tell the
truth.
He called these
prima facie
duties, because when a person tries to decide how to act, each of
these duties need to be taken into consideration when deciding
which duty should be acted upon. When more than one of these
'duties' applies to a person in some situation, only one should be
acted upon. Assume, for example, that I promise to watch a movie
with a friend. I now have a prima facie duty to go with her to
watch the movie. However, on my way to pick my friend up, I see a
car accident. The person who was clearly in the wrong insists that
it is the innocent person's fault. I now have a prima facie duty of
justice to wait for the police to arrive at the accident and report
what I saw. What is my duty? Ross would probably say that the duty
of justice trumped the duty of promise-keeping in this instance. I
can, after all, explain the situation to my friend, and make it up
to her somehow. In another situation, however, the duty of
promise-keeping may be more significant than the duty of
justice.
Contemporary deontologists
Contemporary deontologists
include
Thomas
Nagel,
Thomas
Scanlon and
Frances
Kamm.
Frances Kamm's 'Principle of Permissible Harm' is
an effort to derive a deontological constraint which coheres with
our considered case judgments while also relying heavily on Kant's
Categorical Imperative. The Principle states that one may harm in
order to save more if and only if the harm is an effect or an
aspect of the greater good itself. This principle is meant to
address what Kamm feels are most people's considered case
judgments, many of which involve deontological intuitions. For
instance, Kamm argues that we believe it would be impermissible to
kill one person to harvest his organs in order to save the lives of
five others. Yet, we think it is morally permissible to divert a
runaway trolley that would otherwise kill five innocent and
immobile people onto a side track where one innocent and immobile
person will be killed. Kamm believes the Principle of Permissible
Harm explains the moral difference between these and other cases,
and more importantly expresses a constraint telling us exactly when
we may not act to bring about good ends—such as in the organ
harvesting case.
In 2007, Kamm published a book that presents new
theory that incorporates aspects of her 'Principle of Permissible
Harm', the 'Doctrine of Productive Purity'. Like the 'Principle of
Permissible Harm', the 'Doctrine of Productive Purity' is an
attempt to provide a deontological prescription for determining the
circumstances in which people are permitted to act in a way that
harms others.
Criticism
The most pressing difficulty for deontologist
philosophers is justifying constraints.
Robert
Nozick famously points out what has become known as the
paradox of deontology. If we are truly concerned about rights
(such as the right not to be harmed in certain ways expressed by
Kamm's Principle of Permissible Harm) then it seems logical we
should seek to minimize violations of these rights. However,
deontological constraints themselves prohibit such action. For
example, consider a case where someone has maliciously sent a
trolley hurtling towards five innocent and immobile people at the
end of a track. The only way to stop the trolley and save the five
is to throw one innocent bystander in front of the trolley. If the
five are killed, this would constitute five violations of the PPH.
If the one is thrown in the way, this constitutes one violation of
the PPH. However, the Principle of Permissible Harm clearly rules
out throwing one in front of the trolley. Hence the paradox. In
order to respect the rights of the five, deontologists tell us we
must respect the rights of the one.
Many
Act or
Case utilitarians offer critiques of deontology as well as
Rule
Utilitarianism.
Jeremy
Bentham, an early utilitarian philosopher, criticized
deontology on the grounds that it was essentially a dressed-up
version of popular morality, and that the unchanging principles
that deontologists attribute to natural law or universal reason are
really a matter of subjective opinion.
John
Stuart Mill, who lived in 19th century
Britain, argued that deontologists usually fail to specify
which principles should take priority when rights and duties
conflict, so that deontology cannot offer complete moral
guidance.
Further, Mill argued in the opening pages of his
book Utilitarianism that the Categorical Imperative that Kant had
formulated to support the duties he had argued as categorical in
fact used consequential logic; if the ends of a formulated maxim
logically supported the maxim, that is, the maxim if universalised
created a theoretical world that could exist and would be
beneficial to society, then the maxim could be offered as a rule
under which society should live. Mill criticised Kant for avoiding
saying what the Imperative reduced to - the ends justify the means,
a primary tenet of consequentialism - and thus using it to come to
the opposite conclusion.
Shelly
Kagan, notes in support of Mill and Bentham that under
deontology, individuals are bound by constraints (such as the
requirement not to murder), but are also given options (such as the
right not to give money to charity, if they do not wish to). His
line of attack on deontology is first to show that constraints are
invariably immoral, and then to show that options are immoral
without constraints.
Another, unrelated critique of deontological
ethics comes from
aretaic
theories, which often maintain that neither consequences nor duties
but "character" should be the focal point of ethical theory. The
ancient Greek philosopher
Aristotle, for
example, sought to describe what characteristics a virtuous person
would have, and then argued that people should act in accordance
with these characteristics.
Notes
References
- Beauchamp, Tom L. 1991. Philosophical Ethics: An Introduction
to Moral Philosophy, 2nd Ed. New York: McGraw Hill.
- Broad, C. D. 1930. Five Types of Ethical Theory. New York:
Harcourt, Brace and Co.
- Flew, Antony. 1979. 'Consequentialism'. In A Dictionary of
Philosophy, (2nd Ed.). New York: St Martins.
- Kamm, F. M. 1996. Morality, Mortality Vol. II: Rights, Duties,
and Status. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Kamm, F. M. 2007. Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities,
and Permissible Harm. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN
0195189698.
- Groundwork of the Metaphysic of
Morals
- Olson, Robert G. 1967. 'Deontological Ethics'. In Paul Edwards
(ed.) The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Collier Macmillan.
- Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
- Salzmann, Todd A. 1995. Deontology and Teleology: An
Investigation of the Normative Debate in Roman Catholic Moral
Theology. University Press.
- Waller, Bruce N. 2005. Consider Ethics: Theory, Readings, and
Contemporary Issues. New York: Pearson Longman.
- Wierenga, Edward. 1983. 'A Defensible Divine Command Theory'.
Noûs, 17 (3): 387-407.
External links
deontologist in Danish: Deontologi
deontologist in German: Deontologische
Ethik
deontologist in Spanish: Deontología
deontologist in French: Éthique
déontologique
deontologist in Italian: Deontologia
deontologist in Hebrew: דאונטולוגיה
deontologist in Dutch: Deontologie
deontologist in Norwegian: Deontologi
deontologist in Polish: Deontologia
deontologist in Portuguese: Deontologia
deontologist in Russian: Деонтология
deontologist in Slovak: Deontológia
deontologist in Finnish: Deontologia
deontologist in Swedish:
pliktetik